The Distributive Justice of the Market - Part I

Written by Sam Vaknin


Continued from page 1

In a "Theory of Justice" (published 1971, p. 302), John Rawls described an ideal society thus:

"(1) Each person is to have an equal right torepparttar most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all. (2) Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both: (a) torepparttar 132659 greatest benefit ofrepparttar 132660 least advantaged, consistent withrepparttar 132661 just savings principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity."

It all harks back to scarcity of resources - land, money, raw materials, manpower, creative brains. Those who can afford to do so, hoard resources to offset anxiety regarding future uncertainty. Others wallow in paucity. The distribution of means is thus skewed. "Distributive justice" deals withrepparttar 132662 just allocation of scarce resources.

Yet, evenrepparttar 132663 basic terminology is somewhat fuzzy. What constitutes a resource? what is meant by allocation? Who should allocate resources - Adam Smith's "invisible hand",repparttar 132664 government,repparttar 132665 consumer, or business? Should it reflect differences in power, in intelligence, in knowledge, or in heredity? Should resource allocation be subject to a principle of entitlement? Is it reasonable to demand that it be just - or merely efficient? Are justice and efficiency antonyms?

Justice is concerned with equal access to opportunities. Equal access does not guarantee equal outcomes, invariably determined by idiosyncrasies and differences between people. Access leveraged byrepparttar 132666 application of natural or acquired capacities - translates into accrued wealth. Disparities in these capacities lead to discrepancies in accrued wealth.

The doctrine of equal access is founded onrepparttar 132667 equivalence of Men. That all men are created equal and deserverepparttar 132668 same respect and, therefore, equal treatment is not self evident. European aristocracy well into this century would have probably found this notion abhorrent. Jose Ortega Y Gasset, writing inrepparttar 132669 1930's, preached that access to educational and economic opportunities should be premised on one's lineage, up bringing, wealth, and social responsibilities.

A succession of societies and cultures discriminated againstrepparttar 132670 ignorant, criminals, atheists, females, homosexuals, members of ethnic, religious, or racial groups,repparttar 132671 old,repparttar 132672 immigrant, andrepparttar 132673 poor. Communism - ostensibly a strict egalitarian idea - foundered because it failed to reconcile strict equality with economic and psychological realities within an impatient timetable.

(continued)

Sam Vaknin is the author of Malignant Self Love - Narcissism Revisited and After the Rain - How the West Lost the East. He is a columnist for Central Europe Review, United Press International (UPI) and eBookWeb and the editor of mental health and Central East Europe categories in The Open Directory, Suite101 and searcheurope.com.

Visit Sam's Web site at http://samvak.tripod.com




Abortion and the Right to Life - Part I

Written by Sam Vaknin


Continued from page 1

The answer is yes and no.

No one has a right to sustain his or her life, maintain, or prolong them at another INDIVIDUAL's expense (no matter how minimal and insignificantrepparttar sacrifice required is). Still, if a contract has been signed - implicitly or explicitly - betweenrepparttar 132656 parties, then such a right may crystallize inrepparttar 132657 contract and create corresponding duties and obligations, moral, as well as legal.

Example:

No fetus has a right to sustain its life, maintain, or prolong them at his mother's expense (no matter how minimal and insignificantrepparttar 132658 sacrifice required of her is). Still, if she signed a contract withrepparttar 132659 fetus - by knowingly and willingly and intentionally conceiving it - such a right has crystallized and has created corresponding duties and obligations ofrepparttar 132660 mother towards her fetus.

Onrepparttar 132661 other hand, everyone has a right to sustain his or her life, maintain, or prolong them at SOCIETY's expense (no matter how major and significantrepparttar 132662 resources required are). Still, if a contract has been signed - implicitly or explicitly - betweenrepparttar 132663 parties, thenrepparttar 132664 abrogation of such a right may crystallize inrepparttar 132665 contract and create corresponding duties and obligations, moral, as well as legal.

Example:

Everyone has a right to sustain his or her life, maintain, or prolong them at society's expense. Public hospitals, state pension schemes, and police forces may be required to fulfill society's obligations - but fulfill them it must, no matter how major and significantrepparttar 132666 resources are. Still, if a person volunteered to joinrepparttar 132667 army and a contract has been signed betweenrepparttar 132668 parties, then this right has been thus abrogated andrepparttar 132669 individual assumed certain duties and obligations, includingrepparttar 132670 duty or obligation to give up his or her life to society.

ID. The Right not to be Killed

Every person hasrepparttar 132671 right not to be killed unjustly. What constitutes "just killing" is a matter for an ethical calculus inrepparttar 132672 framework of a social contract.

But does A's right not to be killed includerepparttar 132673 right against third parties that they refrain from enforcingrepparttar 132674 rights of other people against A? Does A's right not to be killed precluderepparttar 132675 righting of wrongs committed by A against others - even ifrepparttar 132676 righting of such wrongs meansrepparttar 132677 killing of A?

Not so. There is a moral obligation to right wrongs (to restorerepparttar 132678 rights of other people). If A maintains or prolongs his life ONLY by violatingrepparttar 132679 rights of others and these other people object to it - then A must be killed if that isrepparttar 132680 only way to rightrepparttar 132681 wrong and re-assert their rights.

(continued)

Sam Vaknin is the author of Malignant Self Love - Narcissism Revisited and After the Rain - How the West Lost the East. He is a columnist for Central Europe Review, United Press International (UPI) and eBookWeb and the editor of mental health and Central East Europe categories in The Open Directory, Suite101 and searcheurope.com.

Visit Sam's Web site at http://samvak.tripod.com




    <Back to Page 1
 
ImproveHomeLife.com © 2005
Terms of Use